Bertrand Russell’s Paradox Explained

How did Bertrand Russell’s paradox shake the foundations of mathematics and logic?

Dec 22, 2022By Luke Dunne, BA Philosophy & Theology

bertrand russell paradox explained

 

Bertrand Russell, one of the most influential mathematicians, logicians, and philosophers of the 20th century, gives his name to one of the most famous and influential logical paradoxes of the modern period. Whereas some of the ancient paradoxes, most famously those developed by Zeno, are concerned with problems of logic or reasoning as such, Russell’s paradox is a problem for a more limited set of theories in logic, in particular those which are known as ‘naïve set theories’. In this article, we will explore this paradox, the historical context in which it appeared and its consequences on philosophy and logic.

 

Introducing Russell’s Paradox

bertrand russell photograph
A photograph of Bertrand Russell in 1957, via Wikimedia Commons.

 

As we already mentioned, Russell’s paradox concerns naïve set theory. ‘Naïve’ here isn’t pejorative, but merely serves to distinguish them from axiomatic theories (which precede from axioms defined in formal logic). Formal logic here refers to any attempt to examine arguments and reasoning which involves rendering them in formal languages, which are artificial and created specifically for the purpose of studying reasoning and arguments. This is in contrast to informal logic, which studies arguments and reasoning by focusing on natural languages, like English.

 

Naïve set theories begin with informal definitions; those we find in natural languages, and not the formal logical languages which mathematicians or logicians (philosophers who study logic) invent for themselves.

 

The Crux of the Paradox 

young bertrand russell photograph
Bertrand Russell as a (fairly) young man, photograph in 1916 in “Justice in War-Time”.

 

Get the latest articles delivered to your inbox

Sign up to our Free Weekly Newsletter

The crux of the paradox concerns sets which appear to be both members of themselves, and not members of themselves. Rather than initially setting the paradox out in the terms in which mathematicians and logicians tend to think about it, we can begin by examining a more informal example.

 

Consider the barber paradox: Imagine a barber who shaves all the men in a village who do not shave themselves, and only those men who do not shave themselves. Does the barber shave himself? If we say, ‘No’, then he is a man in this village who doesn’t shave himself, and so who must shave him? The barber! But he is the barber, so he does actually shave himself. If we say, ‘Yes’, then he is a man who shaves himself, so he can’t be shaved by the barber, but that means he in fact does not shave himself, and so on.

 

This might seem like a harmless curiosity of natural expression, and it might seem to solve the problem to simply reply: ‘no such barber can possibly exist’. However, this paradox is not harmless as far as logicians and mathematicians are concerned. In fact, although some of the implications of the paradox are still disputed. The immediate consequences included the discovery of a major vulnerability in the most promising attempts to underpin mathematics using formal logic.

 

Russell’s Paradox, Frege’s Project

frege bronze bust plinth
A bronze bust of Gottlob Frege

 

Bertrand Russell developed Russell’s paradox broadly in response to the work of Gottlob Frege, a German mathematician, logician and philosopher. Specifically, Russell raised the paradox as a response to the concept of sets used by Frege in the articulation of his overall, lifelong project, which was an attempt to show that mathematics was reducible to logic.

 

There isn’t space to cover the precise function of the set within Frege’s overall project here, but we can succinctly summarize his theory of sets as follows. For Frege, sets correspond in relation of one to one with properties. There corresponds to each property a set of things which have said property. For instance, the set corresponding to the property of ‘being the winner of the 2021 Men’s Ballon d’Or’ would have one member, namely Lionel Messi. What we must bear in mind about this theory moving forwards is that it adheres to what has come to be known as the ‘unrestricted comprehension principle’. To put it simply, that principle holds that for any property, there is a set of all and only the objects which have that property.

 

Sophisticated Sets

russell home bloomsbury
A photograph of Russell’s home in Bloomsbury, London

 

Not all sets are as straightforward as the examples we just mentioned, and it is important to observe some of the philosophical issues raised by this conception of sets. Consider the question of what is contained within the set corresponding to the property of being red, i.e the set containing all red things. There are not infinitely many things in the universe, and so the set is not infinitely large. It is hypothetical, given we do not know of every red thing, and we may not even in principle know of every red thing. Is such a set conceivable? Is it imaginable?

 

Our theory of color is certainly a factor. How we conceive of this set, if we can conceive of it, will surely depend on whether the quality of being red is determined by facts about human language, human perception or other ‘cognitive’ faculties, or whether red is a natural property. Indeed, to distinguish language from cognition from nature in this way would be inadmissible to many philosophers. Ever finer points of argument are liable to arise when we attempt to characterize sets and properties in this way.

 

Impossible Properties

arturo espinosa illustration russell
An illustration of Bertrand Russell by Arturo Espinosa, 2012, via the author’s Flickr.

 

Whatever the issues with Frege’s theory of sets, it does avoid problems which befall other theories of sets, and in any case it has an important role to play in Frege’s overall theory. So, what was the problem which Russell posed for Frege’s theory? It turned on the notion of sets which are a member of themselves, and a possible contradiction they posed for Frege’s way of thinking about sets.

 

If we consider ‘not being a member of itself’ a property, then the question emerges: is the set of all sets which are not members of themselves (which we can call A), a member of itself? If we answer ‘yes’, we are claiming that A is a member of itself, but of course this makes no sense, because then it is by definition not a member of itself. Equally, if we answer ‘no’, this also makes no sense because it is then by definition a member of itself.

 

A Problem of Comprehensive Classes

gottlob frege grave cross
A photograph of Frege’s grave in Wismar, Germany. Via Wikimedia Commons.

 

There is a related issue concerning comprehensive classes. Russell puts the point this way: “The comprehensive class we are considering, which is to embrace everything, must embrace itself as one of its members. In other words, if there is such a thing as “everything,” then, “everything” is something, and is a member of the class “everything.” But normally a class is not a member of itself. Mankind, for example, is not a man. Form now the assemblage of all classes which are not members of themselves. This is a class: is it a member of itself or not? If it is, it is one of those classes that are not members of themselves, i.e., it is not a member of itself. If it is not, it is not one of those classes that are not members of themselves, i.e. it is a member of itself. Thus of the two hypotheses – that it is, and that it is not, a member of itself – each implies its contradictory. This is a contradiction.”

 

A Word on Frege

photograph trinity college cambridge
A photograph of Trinity College Cambridge, where Russell taught, via Wikimedia Commons.

 

Before moving on, it is worth putting in a word for Frege, both as a philosopher and as a human being. Frege’s project of reducing mathematics to logic was, undoubtedly, unsuccessful. Yet Frege was far from a philosophical failure. Over the past century or so, he has proven to be one of, if not the, most important philosophers of logic, mathematics and language.

 

Michael Dummett, a prominent philosopher in his own right, takes the view that all ‘analytic’ philosophy, the dominant strand practiced in English speaking universities, should really be called ‘Post-Fregean philosophy’, so influential was Frege on the course of its development. Russell brought the paradox to Frege’s attention just as the second edition of Frege’s Basic Laws of Arithmetic was going to the press.

 

Frege’s Magnanimity

gottingen frege memorial plaque
A plaque dedicated to Frege in Göttingen, where he studied and taught. Via Wikimedia Commons.

 

Frege was known for his affability and sense of collegial duty. He is responsible, among other things, for Ludwig Wittgenstein’s decision to work with Russell at Cambridge. This paradox, as Frege must have known, threatened to undermine not just his entire book, but the project to which he had devoted his entire productive life. It is worth emphasizing how astonishingly magnanimous Frege’s response was, which Bertrand Russell himself described thus:

 

“His entire life’s work was on the verge of completion, much of his work had been ignored to the benefit of men infinitely less capable, his second volume was about to be published, and upon finding that his fundamental assumption was in error, he responded with intellectual pleasure clearly submerging any feelings of personal disappointment. It was almost superhuman and a telling indication of that of which men are capable if their dedication is to creative work and knowledge instead of cruder efforts to dominate and be known”. It is difficult to begrudge such a person’s continued intellectual importance and standing among philosophers today.

 

The Significance of Russell’s Paradox: We Can Infer Anything from a Contradiction! 

whitehead black and white photograph
A photograph of A.N Whitehead, who collaborated with Russell. Via the Wellcome Collection.

 

The significance of Russell’s paradox can be felt when we realize that anything follows from a contradiction, which is not obvious at first glance. It is hard to demonstrate this here, but follow this basic framework from classical logic:

 

If there is a contradiction, then that is the same as saying that P, and yet, at the same time, not-P, where P is just any sentence with a truth value. P could be, for instance, the sentence: ‘Frege is a logician’. It is a contradiction to say both ‘Frege is a logician’, and ‘Frege is not a logician’. If we assume both P and not-P, we can make any sentence follow from this in the following way:

 

If P is true, then it is necessarily true that one of P or Q (some other sentence) are true; after all, we know P is true already, so even if Q is false, one of the two sentences is true, so one of P or Q is true. But given we are also assuming that not-P is true, and we have shown that one of P or Q is true, we are bound to say that Q is true. This is insane and must not happen! We have no idea what Q is; it could be a completely nonsensical or utterly implausible sentence, and yet we would be bound to say that it is true according to the most basic laws of logic. Such is the power of the contradiction.

 

Plausible Responses to Russell’s Paradox 

david hilbert photograph
A photograph of David Hilbert in 1907, via the American Journal of Mathematics.

 

A range of responses to Russell’s paradox have been offered. One of the more natural solutions was offered by Russell himself. Russell’s own response, developed along with A.N Whitehead, seeks to avoid the paradox by arranging all sentences into a kind of hierarchy, and holding that it is possible to refer to all objects under a given condition only if they are of the same level or type. The stated purpose of this is to avoid so-called ‘vicious circles’ which arise from what they describe as, “a collection of objects may contain members which can only be defined by means of the collection as a whole.”

 

This general strategy arises from the view that no function can be applied to objects presupposing the function itself. This therefore constitutes a kind of hierarchy of operation, which allows us to retain what is useful about the notion of the set. This is not the only viable approach. David Hilbert, for instance, takes what is known as the ‘formalist’ view, which advocates using only finite, well-defined objects. A final approach, that of ‘intuitionism’, developed by Luitzen Brower, holds that one cannot assert that a mathematical object exists unless one can describe the procedure by which it can be constructed.

Author Image

By Luke DunneBA Philosophy & TheologyLuke is a graduate of the University of Oxford's departments of Philosophy and Theology, his main interests include the history of philosophy, the metaphysics of mind, and social theory.